Truth

Copyright © 2008 William Meacham. Permission to reproduce is granted provided the work is reproduced in its entirety, including this notice. Contact the author at http://www.bmeacham.com.

Click here for the PDF version, better for printing and reading offline.

Contents

Introduction

Congruence

Consistency

Coherence

Usefulness

Confidence

Non-Falsifiable Theories

What Is Knowable and What Is Believable

Revision History

Introduction

How do we know any of this is true? There are several factors that determine the truthfulness of a theory or an explanation of events:

I am in the pragmatist camp here. I think the chief quality of a theory that causes us to believe it, that is, to act as if it is true, is its usefulness. Let's look at each of these characteristics in turn.

Congruence

Congruence is correspondence. Truth is said to be a quality of propositions such that they correspond to reality. If someone says the car is in the driveway, we can go look at the driveway to see if the car is really there. What’s true, on this view, is an accurate reflection or statement of reality. But we don’t have direct contact with reality, where “reality” means something completely independent of us. We have direct contact only with our experience, and our contact with reality is filtered through our experience. When what we experience is predictable, and our actions have favorable results, then we can infer that what we are basing our actions on is true. Our theory is congruent with the facts, as we experience them.

Consistency

A good theory is one all the elements of which hang together; it contains no contradictions. An inconsistent theory has little or no predictive value. If elements of the theory contradict themselves, one can’t make consistent logical inferences from the theory. One can make inferences, but they are contradictory, and one does not know which inference to base one’s actions on. An inconsistent theory is not useful.

Related to consistency is simplicity. The recommendation to simplify theory is called Occam’s Razor.1 The simpler a theory is, the more easily disprovable and the more easily understandable it is.

Coherence

A consistent theory is coherent with other theories. We take as true those assertions, ideas or theories that cohere with all the rest of what we take as true, including our empirical observations as well as our theoretical knowledge. (We should always be ready, however, to revise such judgments on the basis of new information, else we risk falling into dogmatism.) A good example of this attribute of truth is found in the physical sciences. The theories of physical science hold together quite well. Physics, chemistry, geology, biology and astronomy all reinforce each other.

Usefulness

An essential characteristic of truth is that it increases our mastery of our lives and environment; it enables us to exert our power, in the sense of our ability to get things done. I include in the term “environment” both the world of physical things and the world of ideas, of theory. What is true is what works to organize our practice and our thought, so that we are able both to handle reality effectively and to reason with logical rigor to true conclusions.

The physical sciences exemplify this attribute of truth. The scientific method is a method of evidence-based argument consisting of systematic observation and explanation. Since observation is central, assertions must include reports of the data on which they are based, including enough description of how the data was acquired to enable others to acquire similar data and look for alternative explanations. What authorizes belief is objective confirmation (or contradiction) of expected results by independent observers. The more rigorous the specification of expected results, the more compelling the confirmation (or contradiction). In other words, a theory we take to be true is useful in that it enables us to make predictions that are verified by further observation.

The authority structure of science is anarchic, with scientists deciding for themselves whom and what to believe. The occasional data fakers, professors who tyrannize their graduate students, or national academies that install an orthodoxy pretty quickly get outrun by events. The result is an accumulation of theories (i.e., systematic explanations) that are better established than anything else in human experience (although still incomplete -- perhaps with big holes in some areas).2

If multiple theories explain the observations, we choose the one that explains more of the observations or explains them with more precision or to a greater level of detail. In other words, we choose the one that is most useful for making further predictions and hence for enabling us to master our lives.

Truth is useful. Does that mean that what is useful is true? That is not a useful question. Let’s not ask what truth is; let’s ask instead how we can recognize it reliably when it appears.

A good theory points out aspects of our experience to which it would be beneficial to pay attention. A good philosophical explanation identifies patterns in our experience. (By “pattern” I mean repeated regularity, a configuration of events or things. This is not the Re-evaluation Counseling meaning of the term, which denotes a subset of patterns in general.)

The relationship between theory and pattern is two-way. Theory describes patterns found in experience, and the patterns found in experience inform theory. We can use other words as well:

Theory         Patterns (regularities)
      ------->
      incorporates
      sees, grasps
      goes out and gets

      <-------
      inform
      are incorporated into
      give input to

Ultimately, truth is good. It works to promote human flourishing. Truth promotes goodness, love, harmony and beauty, both in the short term and in the long term. Truth promotes health.

Confidence

Truth gives us confidence. To believe something to be true is to be willing to act on it and, in fact, actually to act on it when the occasion arises. Confidence alone is not a guarantee of truth. People can have great confidence in something that is false, or at least has bad consequences. People with confidence in what is false have faith, in a disparaging or pejorative sense of the term “faith.” But if someone has clear perception and tends to believe true things, then the higher that person’s confidence in something, the more likely it is to be true. This is the basis in reality for the argument from authority for the truthfulness of propositions.

Non-Falsifiable Theories

Metaphysical theories, theories intended to be universally applicable and to explain all elements of experience and the objects of experience, are not falsifiable. For example, the theory that everything has an inside and an outside – a subjective, privately observable aspect and an objective, publicly observable aspect – cannot be disproved. One cannot prove that some things have no subjective aspect because to do so would require us to observe the inside, the subjectivity, of those things and determine that they had no subjectivity. But by definition we cannot directly observe the subjectivity of anything other than our own.

In cases where a theory is not easily or at all falsifiable, for instance a metaphysical explanation of life, one cannot verify its congruence or correspondence with reality. One can, however, make judgments on the basis of the other criteria. One can decide to act is if it is true or not on the basis of its consistency, its coherence and its practicality for achieving one’s ends.

What Is Knowable and What Is Believable

What we can know from direct experience: That the transcendental Self is unobservable.

What we believe to be true on the basis of the best science to date: That the quantum-mechanical level of reality is indeterminate.

What may be true and does not contradict what we know:

Revision History

Version

Date

Author

Change

1.0

27 July 2008

Bill Meacham

First publication

1.1

28 October 2008

Bill Meacham

Fix minor typo. No substantive change.

1.2

12 February 2010

Bill Meacham

Add note about competing theories.

1 Occam's razor (also spelled Ockham's razor) is a principle attributed to the 14th-century English logician and Franciscan friar William of Ockham. [It is] a heuristic maxim that advises economy, parsimony, or simplicity in scientific theories. Occam's razor states that the explanation of any phenomenon should make as few assumptions as possible, eliminating those that make no difference in the observable predictions of the explanatory hypothesis or theory…. Furthermore, when multiple competing theories have equal predictive powers, the principle recommends selecting those that introduce the fewest assumptions and postulate the fewest hypothetical entities.

2 Thanks to Hunter Ellinger for this insight.

 


Being Human – Table of Contents
What's What
bmeacham.com